What does "Some" mean in coq? - coq

What does the keyword/command "Some" mean in coq?
Furthermore, how can I look up its definition? Using coq some doesn't really help much given popularity of the word some.

Some is a type constructor of the option type. You can get some infos about such constructor by Checking or Printing them, to get their type or their full implementation.
Edit: what is the option type.
It is a type defined in Coq's prelude (again, use Check or Print to get info on this type). The type is used to state facts about the optional presence of a type: for any type A, None : option A means that there is no value, and Some A: option A means that there is a value (of type A).
Here is an example with the predecessor of a natural number:
Definition myPred (n:nat) : option nat := match n with
| S p => Some p
| O => None
end.
In this example, if you try to compute the predecessor of O, you'll get None (there is no such natural number). Otherwise, you get Some p such that S p = n.

Related

What is a concrete example of the type `Set` and what is the meaning of `Set`?

I've been trying to understand what Set is after encountering it in Adam Chlipala's book in addition to this great discussion in SO. His first example definition binary ops using Set:
Inductive binop : Set := Plus | Times.
in that book he says:
Second, there is the : Set fragment, which declares that we are defining a datatype that should be thought of as a constituent of programs.
Which confuses me. What does Adam mean here?
In addition, I thought that some additional concrete examples would help my understanding. I am not an expert of Coq so I am not sure what type of examples would help but something simple and very concrete/grounded might be useful.
Note, I have seen that Set is the first "type set" in a the type hierarchy e.g. Set = Type(0) <= Type = Type(1) <= Type(2) <= ... . I guess this sort of makes sense intuitively like I'd assume nat \in Type and all usual programming types to be in it but not sure what would be in Type that wouldn't be in Set. Perhaps recursive types? Not sure if that is the right example but I am trying to wrap my head around what this concept means and it's conceptual (& practical) usefulness.
Though Set and Type are different in Coq, this is mostly due to historical reasons. Nowadays, most developments do not rely on Set being different from Type. In particular, Adam's comment would also make sense if you replace Set by Type everywhere. The main point is that, when you want to define a datatype that you can compute with during execution (e.g. a number), you want to put it in Set or Type rather than Prop. This is because things that live in Prop are erased when you extract programs from Coq, so something defined in Prop would end up not computing anything.
As for your second question: Set is something that lives in Type, but not in Set, as the following snippet shows.
Check Set : Type. (* This works *)
Fail Check Set : Set.
(* The command has indeed failed with message: *)
(* The term "Set" has type "Type" while it is expected to have type *)
(* "Set" (universe inconsistency: Cannot enforce Set+1 <= Set). *)
This restriction is in place to prevent paradoxes in the theory. This is pretty much the only difference you see between Set and Type by default. You can also make them more different by invoking Coq with the -impredicative-set option:
(* Needs -impredicative-set; otherwise, the first line will also fail.*)
Check (forall A : Set, A -> A) : Set.
Universe u.
Fail Check (forall A : Type#{u}, A -> A) : Type#{u}.
(* The command has indeed failed with message: *)
(* The term "forall A : Type, A -> A" has type "Type#{u+1}" *)
(* while it is expected to have type "Type#{u}" (universe inconsistency: Cannot enforce *)
(* u < u because u = u). *)
Note that I had to add the Universe u. declaration to force the two occurrences of Type to be at the same level. Without this declaration, Coq would silently put the two Types at different universe levels, and the command would be accepted. (This would not mean that Type would have the same behavior as Set in this example, since Type#{u} and Type#{v} are different things when u and v are different!)
If you're wondering why this feature is useful, it is not by chance. The overwhelming majority of Coq developments does not rely on it. It is turned off by default because it is incompatible with a few axioms that are generally considered more useful in Coq developments, such as the strong law of the excluded middle:
forall A : Prop, {A} + {~ A}
With -impredicative-set turned on, this axiom yields a paradox, while it is safe to use by default.

Why does Coq use unnamed parameters in Inductive Types of Propositions?

I was looking at IndProp and I saw:
Fail Inductive wrong_ev (n : nat) : Prop :=
| wrong_ev_0 : wrong_ev 0
| wrong_ev_SS : ∀ n, wrong_ev n → wrong_ev (S (S n)).
(* ===> Error: A parameter of an inductive type n is not
allowed to be used as a bound variable in the type
of its constructor. *)
except that it seems to behave exactly as if it was taking an argument but it seems to throw an error. Why is this?
The text provides some explanation but I don't understand it:
what I don't understand specifically it. The part I don't understand is the part it says:
it is allowed to take different values in the types
why is it saying "in the types"? Types are NOT the input, values are. Why is it saying this? It seems extremely confusing. I know (extremely vaguely) that there is such a thing as "dependent types" but is that what it's referring too? Shouldn't it be arguments? Don't constructors take value or "stuff" and return an object of some type?
Why does it seem that the signature of the Inductive type (which really I just view it as a function that builds things are returns objects of some type) missing the arguments?
More context from text where explanation seems to appear:
This definition is different in one crucial respect from previous uses of Inductive: its result is not a Type, but rather a function from nat to Prop — that is, a property of numbers. Note that we've already seen other inductive definitions that result in functions, such as list, whose type is Type → Type. What is new here is that, because the nat argument of ev appears unnamed, to the right of the colon, it is allowed to take different values in the types of different constructors: 0 in the type of ev_0 and S (S n) in the type of ev_SS.
In contrast, the definition of list names the X parameter globally, to the left of the colon, forcing the result of nil and cons to be the same (list X). Had we tried to bring nat to the left in defining ev, we would have seen an error ... We can think of the definition of ev as defining a Coq property ev : nat → Prop, together with primitive theorems ev_0 : ev 0 and ev_SS : ∀n, ev n → ev (S (S n)).
Such "constructor theorems" have the same status as proven theorems.
why is it saying "in the types"? Types are NOT the input, values are
You need to read the whole expression: "in the types of different constructors".
And, indeed, the natural number is different in the return type of the two constructors:
It is 0 for ev_0
And it is S (S n) for ev_SS

What exactly is a Set in Coq

I'm still puzzled what the sort Set means in Coq. When do I use Set and when do I use Type?
In Hott a Set is defined as a type, where identity proofs are unique.
But I think in Coq it has a different interpretation.
Set means rather different things in Coq and HoTT.
In Coq, every object has a type, including types themselves. Types of types are usually referred to as sorts, kinds or universes. In Coq, the (computationally relevant) universes are Set, and Type_i, where i ranges over natural numbers (0, 1, 2, 3, ...). We have the following inclusions:
Set <= Type_0 <= Type_1 <= Type_2 <= ...
These universes are typed as follows:
Set : Type_i for any i
Type_i : Type_j for any i < j
Like in Hott, this stratification is needed to ensure logical consistency. As Antal pointed out, Set behaves mostly like the smallest Type, with one exception: it can be made impredicative when you invoke coqtop with the -impredicative-set option. Concretely, this means that forall X : Set, A is of type Set whenever A is. In contrast, forall X : Type_i, A is of type Type_(i + 1), even when A has type Type_i.
The reason for this difference is that, due to logical paradoxes, only the lowest level of such a hierarchy can be made impredicative. You may then wonder then why Set is not made impredicative by default. This is because an impredicative Set is inconsistent with a strong form of the axiom of the excluded middle:
forall P : Prop, {P} + {~ P}.
What this axiom allows you to do is to write functions that can decide arbitrary propositions. Note that the {P} + {~ P} type lives in Set, and not Prop. The usual form of the excluded middle, forall P : Prop, P \/ ~ P, cannot be used in the same way, because things that live in Prop cannot be used in a computationally relevant way.
In addition to Arthur's answer:
From the fact that Set is located at the bottom of the hierarchy,
it follows that Set is the type of the “small” datatypes and function types, i.e. the ones whose values do not directly or indirectly involve types.
That means the following will fail:
Fail Inductive Ts : Set :=
| constrS : Set -> Ts.
with this error message:
Large non-propositional inductive types must be in Type.
As the message suggests, we can amend it by using Type:
Inductive Tt : Type :=
| constrT : Set -> Tt.
Reference:
The Essence of Coq as a Formal System by B. Jacobs (2013), pdf.

coq. ordered pair of natual numbers

I am trying to defined an inductive data type to hold pair of natural numbers. Here is what I have done
Definition ordered_pair := (nat * nat) % type.
Inductive nat_pair(A B:nat):ordered_pair:=
|pair :ordered_pair->ordered_pair.
It generates exception
Anomaly: Uncaught exception Reduction.NotArity. Please report.
Does anyone know there?
This inductive definition just does not make sense.
The type ordered_pair you have defined is already a type for pairs of natural numbers.
It is defined as the pair type, applied to arguments of type nat, so to build such a pair you could do:
Definition p : ordered_pair := (23, 42).
Now if you wanted to define a "similar" (but not "identical") type inductively, the syntax would be:
Inductive nat_pair : Set :=
| pair : nat -> nat -> nat_pair
.
Notice that you don't take natural numbers as parameters in the type, but rather the constructor contains two such numbers.
You seem to have some misunderstanding of inductive definitions, so I'd suggest reading more about them.

Kind vs Rank in type theory

I'm having a hard time understanding Higher Kind vs Higher Rank types. Kind is pretty simple (thanks Haskell literature for that) and I used to think rank is like kind when talking about types but apparently not! I read the Wikipedia article to no avail. So can someone please explain what is a Rank? and what is meant by Higher Rank? Higher Rank Polymorphism? how that comes to Kinds (if any) ? Comparing Scala and Haskell would be awesome too.
The concept of rank is not really related to the concept of kinds.
The rank of a polymorphic type system describes where foralls may appear in types. In a rank-1 type system foralls may only appear at the outermost level, in a rank-2 type system they may appear at one level of nesting and so on.
So for example forall a. Show a => (a -> String) -> a -> String would be a rank-1 type and forall a. Show a => (forall b. Show b => b -> String) -> a -> String would be a rank-2 type. The difference between those two types is that in the first case, the first argument to the function can be any function that takes one showable argument and returns a String. So a function of type Int -> String would be a valid first argument (like a hypothetical function intToString), so would a function of type forall a. Show a => a -> String (like show). In the second case only a function of type forall a. Show a => a -> String would be a valid argument, i.e. show would be okay, but intToString wouldn't be. As a consequence the following function would be a legal function of the second type, but not the first (where ++ is supposed to represent string concatenation):
higherRankedFunction(f, x) = f("hello") ++ f(x) ++ f(42)
Note that here the function f is applied to (potentially) three different types of arguments. So if f were the function intToString this would not work.
Both Haskell and Scala are Rank-1 (so the above function can not be written in those languages) by default. But GHC contains a language extension to enable Rank-2 polymorphism and another one to enable Rank-n polymorphism for arbitrary n.